일전에 과외로 생긴 목돈이 있어 베이어 다이내믹스 t5p헤드폰을 구입하였다. 교보 첨음 매장에서 들은 t1의 소리를 잊지 못하고 있다가, 그 동생 뻘로 나온 t5p를 지른 것이다. t1보다 가격이 조금 싸게 형성되어 있고, 아이폰과 같은 소형기기에 직결이 가능하다는 것이 매력이었다. 전철타고 다니면서 쓸 요량으로 구입했지만 그러기에는 사이즈가 너무 커서 결국 연구실에 거치해 놓고 사용하고 있다. 그런데 기대했던 것보다  이 놈의 소리가 마음에 쏙 들지는 않는다. 처음에 집에서 사용하던 grado rs1과 비청을 해보고 소리가 너무가 마음에 들지 않아서 깜짝 놀랐다.

일단 udac2hp라는 소형 dac 를 연결하여 들어보았지만 크게 개선이 되지 않는다. 인터넷에서 udac2에 대한 평이 좋아 샀는데 그렇게 좋은 줄을 모르겠다. 인터넷을 뒤지니 스베트라나2라는 프리 겸용 진공관 헤드폰 앰프에 대한 소문이 자자하다. 이 놈을 들여야만 문제가 해결될까? 그런데 이 놈의 가격이 130만원이다. 허걱.

그러던 차에 udac2의 업그레이드 버전이 나왔고, 성능이 udac2와는 한 차원 다른 소리를 들려준단다. 내친 김에 숙제하는 기분으로 집에 묵혀두었던 루비dac과 집에서 든는 Grado RS1을 학교로 가지고 와서 본격적인 비청을 했다. 그 사이 t5p도 어느 정도 에이징이 되었는지, grado와 비교해 들어도 소리가 크게 떨어지지 않는다.(가격으로 보면 t5p가 더 나아야 하지만.) 소리는 t5p가 훨씬 더 단단하고 정갈하지만, 밀페형이어서 그런지 공간감이 떨어진다. 그래서인지 아직은 음악을  편하게 듣기에는  그라도가  더 좋다. t5p는 소리는 좋지만 왠지 긴장하게 된다.
 
그런데 여기서 놀라운 발견 하나. 그간 별로라고 생각하고 있었던 udac2의 해드폰단이 루비의 헤드폰단보다는 한 수 위이다. 루비는 뭔가 채색된 소리처럼 들리고 소란스러운데 비하여, udac2의  소리가 훨씬 명료하고 차분하다. udac2+t5p만 들었을 때에는 그런 생각을 전혀 해보지 못했는데. 갑자기 udac2se를 들어보고 싶은 욕구가 용솟음친다. 33만원에 공동구매하는 사이트에서 거의 클릭 직전까지 갔다가, 네이버 중고거래 사이트에서 26만원짜리 물건이 하나 나와 있음을 발견했다. 비오는 날 오후 전철을  타고 시청역으로 가서 그 놈을 물어왔다.

떨리는 마음으로 집으로 돌아와 드디어 비청. 처음 터져 나오는 소리를 듣고 깜짝 놀랐다. udac2와는 확연히 구분되는 좋은 소리가 난다. '심봤다.' 마우스보다 더 작은 놈에게서 저런 소리가 나오다니. 시간 가는줄 모르고  늦은 저녁 내내 음악을 들었다. 스베트라나2의 유혹에서 완전히 벗어난 것은 아니지만, 당분간 udac2se만으로도 한동안은 버틸 수 있겠다. 


'디지털 라이프' 카테고리의 다른 글

DAC  (0) 2012.03.09
T5P와 T1, HD800  (3) 2012.03.08
루비  (0) 2010.10.27
아이폰  (0) 2009.12.09
iphone  (0) 2009.12.08
Posted by deanima
,


Posted by deanima
,
SEPTEMBER 4, 2011, 5:00 PM

What Is Naturalism?

The Stone is a forum for contemporary philosophers on issues both timely and timeless.


Many contemporary philosophers describe themselves as naturalists. They mean that they believe something like this: there is only the natural world, and the best way to find out about it is by the scientific method. I am sometimes described as a naturalist. Why do I resist the description? Not for any religious scruple: I am an atheist of the most straightforward kind. But accepting the naturalist slogan without looking beneath the slick packaging is an unscientific way to form one’s beliefs about the world, not something naturalists should recommend.

What, for a start, is the natural world? If we say it is the world of matter, or the world of atoms, we are left behind by modern physics, which characterizes the world in far more abstract terms. Anyway, the best current scientific theories will probably be superseded by future scientific developments. We might therefore define the natural world as whatever the scientific method eventually discovers. Thus naturalism becomes the belief that there is only whatever the scientific method eventually discovers, and (not surprisingly) the best way to find out about it is by the scientific method. That is no tautology. Why can’t there be things only discoverable by non-scientific means, or not discoverable at all?

Still, naturalism is not as restrictive as it sounds. For example, some of its hard-nosed advocates undertake to postulate a soul or a god, if doing so turns out to be part of the best explanation of our experience, for that would be an application of scientific method. Naturalism is not incompatible in principle with all forms of religion. In practice, however, most naturalists doubt that belief in souls or gods withstands scientific scrutiny.

What is meant by “the scientific method”? Why assume that science only has one method? For naturalists, although natural sciences like physics and biology differ from each other in specific ways, at a sufficiently abstract level they all count as using a single general method. It involves formulating theoretical hypotheses and testing their predictions against systematic observation and controlled experiment. This is called the hypothetico-deductive method.

One challenge to naturalism is to find a place for mathematics. Natural sciences rely on it, but should we count it a science in its own right? If we do, then the description of scientific method just given is wrong, for it does not fit the science of mathematics, which proves its results by pure reasoning, rather than the hypothetico-deductive method. Although a few naturalists, such as W.V. Quine, argued that the real evidence in favor of mathematics comes from its applications in the natural sciences, so indirectly from observation and experiment, that view does not fit the way the subject actually develops. When mathematicians assess a proposed new axiom, they look at its consequences within mathematics, not outside. On the other hand, if we do not count pure mathematics a science, we thereby exclude mathematical proof by itself from the scientific method, and so discredit naturalism. For naturalism privileges the scientific method over all others, and mathematics is one of the most spectacular success stories in the history of human knowledge.

Which other disciplines count as science? Logic? Linguistics? History? Literary theory? How should we decide? The dilemma for naturalists is this. If they are too inclusive in what they count as science, naturalism loses its bite. Naturalists typically criticize some traditional forms of philosophy as insufficiently scientific, because they ignore experimental tests. How can they maintain such objections unless they restrict scientific method to hypothetico-deductivism? But if they are too exclusive in what they count as science, naturalism loses its credibility, by imposing a method appropriate to natural science on areas where it is inappropriate. Unfortunately, rather than clarify the issue, many naturalists oscillate. When on the attack, they assume an exclusive understanding of science as hypothetico-deductive. When under attack themselves, they fall back on a more inclusive understanding of science that drastically waters down naturalism. Such maneuvering makes naturalism an obscure article of faith. I don’t call myself a naturalist because I don’t want to be implicated in equivocal dogma. Dismissing an idea as “inconsistent with naturalism” is little better than dismissing it as “inconsistent with Christianity.”

Still, I sympathize with one motive behind naturalism — the aspiration to think in a scientific spirit. It’s a vague phrase, but one might start to explain it by emphasizing values like curiosity, honesty, accuracy, precision and rigor. What matters isn’t paying lip-service to those qualities — that’s easy — but actually exemplifying them in practice — the hard part. We needn’t pretend that scientists’ motives are pure. They are human. Science doesn’t depend on indifference to fame, professional advancement, money, or comparisons with rivals. Rather, truth is best pursued in social environments, intellectual communities, that minimize conflict between such baser motives and the scientific spirit, by rewarding work that embodies the scientific virtues. Such traditions exist, and not just in natural science.

Related More From The Stone

Read previous contributions to this series.

The scientific spirit is as relevant in mathematics, history, philosophy and elsewhere as in natural science. Where experimentation is the likeliest way to answer a question correctly, the scientific spirit calls for the experiments to be done; where other methods — mathematical proof, archival research, philosophical reasoning — are more relevant it calls for them instead. Although the methods of natural science could beneficially be applied more widely than they have been so far, the default assumption must be that the practitioners of a well-established discipline know what they are doing, and use the available methods most appropriate for answering its questions. Exceptions may result from a conservative tradition, or one that does not value the scientific spirit. Still, impatience with all methods except those of natural science is a poor basis on which to identify those exceptions.

Naturalism tries to condense the scientific spirit into a philosophical theory. But no theory can replace that spirit, for any theory can be applied in an unscientific spirit, as a polemical device to reinforce prejudice. Naturalism as dogma is one more enemy of the scientific spirit.

Timothy Williamson is the Wykeham Professor of Logic at Oxford University, a Fellow of the British Academy and a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. He has been a visiting professor at M.I.T. and Princeton. His books include “Vagueness” (1994), “Knowledge and its Limits” (2000) and “The Philosophy of Philosophy” (2007).

Posted by deanima
,